
This article is inspired by the Marxist economist, Alfred Sohn-Rethel’s concept of real abstraction, which has gained attention this century through Slavoj Žižek and Alberto Toscano’s discussions of the concept. Sohn-Rethel argued that “commodity exchange is abstract because it excludes use”.1placeholder “[U]se and exchange are mutually exclusive in time…[E]xchange serves only a change of ownership…In order to make this change possible on a basis of negotiated agreement the physical condition of the commodities…must remain unchanged, or at any rate must be assumed to remain unchanged”.2placeholder Having said so, “[w]hile exchange banishes use from the actions of marketing people, it does not banish it from their minds. However, it must remain confined to their minds, occupying them in their imagination and thoughts only”.3placeholder Exchange is mutually exclusive in time with use: there is no touching, or, more precisely, using the commodities before the sales and purchases have been completed, but, as we engage in exchange, we are preoccupied with use. Use has brought us to the market, as we seek to acquire commodities we can use, and would deliver us out of the market, as we leave to use the commodities we have bought. The aim of exchange, i.e. the acquisition of usable commodities, occupies our mind as we engage in exchange. Sohn-Rethel continues to argue our preoccupation with use prevents us from realizing the abstractness of exchange, or its mutual exclusion with use. “One could say that the abstractness of their action is beyond realisation by the actors because their very consciousness stands in the way”.4placeholder
This is an ingenious description of commodity exchange, but I must also raise a trivial objection against it: we are rarely so preoccupied with the objects of our imagination that we fail to realize these objects are objects of our imagination and attribute material reality to the objects. Hence, we, strictly speaking, should be able to realize, as we engage in exchange, that the activity we are engaging in is not the uses which occupy our mind. Having said so, we rarely realize so, and, even after realizing so, the realization seems to contribute nothing to our activity of exchange. Sohn-Rethel’s concept of real abstraction and my discovery of this complacency of my consciousness of exchange inspired this article.
1. Use within our community
“A commodity is, in the first place, an object outside us, a thing that by its properties satisfies human wants of some sort or another”.5placeholder
-
- Things confront us, in the first place, not as objects distinct from ourselves, but as invitations to actions, or, more precisely, uses: things which can be used to satisfy our hunger, thirst, and the like needs, so that we can continue to engage in other practical activities, among others, for the sake of others, and so forth.
- Others confront us, within these invitations to uses, as others with whom we engage in practical activities.
- We realize these invitations in practical activities among others.
- Our practical activities are activities which, satisfying our needs, enable other practical activities, and which themselves are enabled by previous practical activities.
- Things break, and, in general, cease to be usable in our practical activities. These things fall out of the original unity of ourselves, things, and others in the invitations to uses and uses, and confront us as objects distinct from ourselves, or, rather, from the unity of ourselves, usable things, and others. Contra these non-usable things, or objects, this unity becomes a subject.
2. Exchange between communities
In order for exchange to occur, “it is…necessary for men, by a tacit understanding, to treat each other as private owners of those alienable objects, and by implication as independent individuals. But such a state of reciprocal independence has no existence in a primitive society based on property in common…The exchange of commodities, therefore, first begins on the boundaries of such communities, at their points of contact with other similar communities, or with members of the latter”.6placeholder
-
- Two communities come into contact and enter into exchange with the other.
- Exchange is the exchange of things which are not usable for us but usable for the other, for things which are not usable for the other but usable for us.7placeholder
- Members of the other community confront us as others distinct from ourselves, i.e. as foreigners whose needs are distinct from ours.
- Things of the other community confront us as objects distinct from ourselves, i.e. things we cannot make use of.
- In exchange, these objects and the object which is already found in our community, i.e. non-usable things in our community, become constituted by the subject, i.e. the unity of ourselves, usable things, and others. These objects are rendered objects which are for our sake. In exchange, we provide members of the other community with things, or commodities, which satisfy their needs. This, however, is in order to acquire from the other things, or commodities, which satisfy our own needs. Hence, the needs of the foreign other, distinct from our own, become for our sake in the sense that the satisfaction of these needs enable us to satisfy our own needs. The things of the other commodity, becoming commodities also become for our sake, as commodities with which our needs are satisfied. The non-usable things within our community, likewise, become for our sake, as commodities exchangeable for the other’s commodities, with which we satisfy our needs.
3. Self-consciousness
-
- In exchange, the needs of the other, their things, and the non-usable things within our community no longer confront us as mere objects distinct from us, but as objects distinct from us which have been rendered objects for us, or, rather, for our sake.
- In our confrontation with these constituted objects, we are confronted with ourselves, or, rather, the activity by which we constitute these objects, i.e. exchange. Self-consciousness emerges.
4. Implicit negativity of self-consciousness
“They do not know it, but they do it”.8placeholder
-
- In our self-consciousness, or, rather, our consciousness of our activity of exchange, we are necessarily preoccupied with use. The uses the other can put our commodities to and the uses we can put the other’s commodities to determine if exchange is completed. These uses necessarily occupy our mind.
- In simultaneity, we realize these uses which occupy our mind in exchange have not occurred and cannot occur until after exchange has been completed: there is no using the commodities until after exchange has been completed.
- We can, therefore, conclude these uses cannot be exchange and vice versa, as, first, as we engage in exchange, these uses have not occurred and cannot occur until after exchange has been completed, whereas exchange does occur. Second, these uses are activities which satisfy our and the other’s needs, whereas exchange, as the activity which precedes and enables these uses, is an activity where our and the other’s needs are unsatisfied.
- We, however, do not arrive at this conclusion due to our preoccupation with use.
- A second conclusion is also not arrived at due to our failure to arrive at the first: our consciousness of exchange is a negative one which occupies us with what exchange is not, i.e. uses, and tells us nothing of what exchange is.
5. Hoarding and the consciousness of consciousness
-
- Implicit negativity of our consciousness of exchange is realizable only through reflection on our consciousness of exchange, or our consciousness of our consciousness of exchange. The condition for the realization of this implicit negativity is the development of our activities of use and exchange to a stage which requires us to be conscious of our consciousness of exchange.
- We arrive at this stage in the emergence of the desire for money and the concomitant practice of hoarding.
- The desire for money should not be mistaken for the desire to acquire money in order to spend this money purchasing commodities for uses and satisfaction of our needs. Rather, the desire for money has, as its object, the exchangeability of money for other commodities.9placeholder
- As exchange begins between communities, non-usable things within the communities become exchangeable commodities. In a monetary economy, the exchangeability of commodities takes the form of their sellability. Before a sale, the sellability of commodities, or the quantity of money they can sell for, is estimated by their owners. This sellability is further inscribed onto the commodities as their prices.10placeholder
- Estimations of sellability in both communities produce a list of prices. This list, inverted, informs members of both communities of the exchangeability of their money for other commodities, i.e. the myriad commodities their money can purchase them.11placeholder
- Exchangeability of commodities for money and money for commodities are realized, respectively, in sales and purchases. Exchangeability of commodities for money, is, however, not guaranteed to be realized, as the other is not guaranteed to find the commodities on sale usable. In lieu of the most complete knowledge of the practical relations and needs within the community the other belongs to, the seller cannot know for certain their commodities would sell.12placeholder
- Exchangeability of money for other commodities, on the other hand, is guaranteed to be realized by agreement between the two communities. Purchases, unlike sales, are guaranteed to succeed. This realization, however, is also the loss and bastardization of this exchangeability. As money is spent in purchases, money and the exchangeability invested in money are transferred from our hands to the other’s. In simultaneity, we never purchase every commodity money can purchase us. We purchase, only, a limited variety of commodities, as our purchases are determined not only by the virtually boundless exchangeability of money, but also the quantity of money we have at hand, our needs of the time, and so on.13placeholder
- Purchases confront the desire for money as its enemy, because purchases are both the loss and bastardization of the object of this desire, i.e. the social right invested in money which enables its owner to exchange money, without the uncertainty of a sale, for any commodity in the market, or the exchangeability of money.
- Practice of hoarding arises from the desire for money. Hoarder, or miser, sells their commodities not in order to acquire money and purchase commodities for use and satisfaction of their needs, but, solely, to acquire this money.14placeholder The miser accumulates this money through repeated sales and, no less importantly, abstinence from purchases and the satisfaction of their own needs.15placeholder Money spent on commodities for use and their own needs is money lost and not added to their hoard.
- Having said so, the miser still has to satisfy their hunger, thirst, and other basic needs. Therefore, the miser engages in two modes of exchange: a practical mode of exchange which aims at the acquisition of commodities for use and satisfaction of their needs, and hoarding. The abstinence of the miser is abstinence from the former mode of exchange, which confronts the miser as an enemy they both cannot avoid and must suppress.
- A consciousness of consciousness of exchange emerges whenever the miser engages in the practical mode of exchange in order to satisfy their basic needs. Or, more precisely, a consciousness which bemoans the necessity of the practical mode of exchange and their loss of money. The condition for the realization of the implicit negativity of their consciousness of (the practical mode of) exchange is secured by the practice of hoarding.
- To have secured the condition for the realization of the implicit negativity of their consciousness of exchange is also to have secured the condition for the development of economic theories. Consciousness, realizing it has no positive knowledge of exchange, seeks to gain positive knowledge of exchange. From this, Aristotle’s argument, “exchange cannot take place without equality, and equality not without commensurability”16placeholder, and subsequent puzzlement over this commensurability, Adam Smith’s distinction between “value in use” and “exchange”7placeholder, and labor theory of value, Marx and Engels’ materialist conception of history, and so forth, may have emerged.
- The desire for money should not be mistaken for the desire to acquire money in order to spend this money purchasing commodities for uses and satisfaction of our needs. Rather, the desire for money has, as its object, the exchangeability of money for other commodities.9placeholder
6. Conflict of operative and reflective consciousnesses
-
- On the realization of the implicit negativity of our consciousness of exchange, a conflict of consciousnesses emerges. The consciousness which realizes this implicit negativity (reflective consciousness) looks upon our consciousness of exchange (operative consciousness) with contempt, as an incomplete self-consciousness which has failed to secure positive knowledge of every activity we engage in.
- As we engage in exchange again and fall, habitually, back into this incomplete self-consciousness, this incomplete self-consciousness also looks back upon the reflective consciousness with contempt, as an impractical consciousness. Exchange only requires us to be preoccupied with what exchange is not, i.e. use. Our operative consciousness is sufficient for us to engage in exchange. Reflective consciousness contributes nothing to exchange.
- Examples of the latter side of the conflict are myriad: in general, the gap between theory and practice and the difficulty of applying theory to practice, more concretely, the habit of workers to consume theory as entertainment or spiritual empowerment without putting it to practice, the inattentional blindness of intellectuals to the economic structures within which they publish their theories, and so forth.

7. Resolution of the conflict of consciousnesses
-
- This conflict of consciousnesses is unresolvable through simple coercion of operative consciousness from without, i.e. by reflective consciousness. Operative consciousness is a philistine which mocks everything impractical and prides itself on its sacrifice of every wisdom for the sake of practicality.
- The conflict of consciousnesses is also unresolvable through the sale of the discovery of reflective consciousness, e.g. in an overpriced academic book. At first glance, selling the discovery of reflective consciousness enters this discovery into operative consciousness as a commodity whose usability for the other and exchangeability for money must be estimated. Having said so, the sale of this discovery, or, rather, the operative consciousness of this sale, still contains an implicit negativity reflective consciousness must, again, discover. If this second negativity is also sold, the operative consciousness of this sale would contain a third negativity reflective consciousness, again, discovers. Infinite regress ensues.
- The resolution to the conflict of consciousnesses must be found in operative consciousness itself. Reflective consciousness, reflecting on operative consciousness, finds consciousness to not be static but in motion. Our operative consciousness of exchange changes as the mode of exchange we engage in changes.
- In the transition from the practical mode of exchange to hoarding, our preoccupation with use changes. We remain preoccupied with the uses the other can put our commodities to, as the usability of our commodities for the other determines if the other purchases our commodities. Having said so, our preoccupation with our own uses changes. As we engage in hoarding, we do not aim to acquire commodities for use and satisfaction of needs. Rather, this aim of the practical mode of exchange, and the purchases of commodities to achieve this aim, confront us as our enemy, in other words, as an other which cannot be incorporated into hoarding.
- In the transition from the practical mode of exchange to hoarding, the implicit negativity within our operative consciousness, which is the source of the conflict of consciousnesses, diminishes and becomes explicit in parts. The implicit negativity of our operative consciousness of the practical mode of exchanging consists of our failure to arrive at two conclusions: first, the uses which occupy our mind cannot be exchange and vice versa. Second, having failed to arrive at the first conclusion, we fail, also, to conclude our (operative) consciousness of exchange is a negative one which occupies us with what exchange is not and tells us nothing of what exchange is. In the transition to our operative consciousness of hoarding, the first conclusion, or the mutual exclusion of exchange and use, becomes explicit in parts. In our operative consciousness of hoarding, we find hoarding and the aim of the practical mode of exchange, i.e. our uses of commodities we purchase, to be mutually exclusive. In simultaneity, of course, our preoccupation with the other’s uses remains and continues to prevent us from arriving at the conclusion exchange cannot be the other’s uses and vice versa.
- In our operative consciousness of hoarding, the resolution to the conflict of consciousnesses is glimpsed. If we transit to a mode, or modes, of exchange which is expressly impractical, and the concomitant operative consciousness which cognizes the mutual exclusion of these modes of exchange from every use, the conflict of consciousnesses is resolved at its source, i.e. the implicit negativity reflective consciousness discovers in our operative consciousness of the practical mode of exchange.
- Having said so, the movement of operative consciousness continues in a further transition to capital and the resolution glimpsed in the operative consciousness of hoarding vanishes from sight. The capitalist is a “rational miser”18placeholder, of dialectical reason, who appropriates the other of the miser, i.e. purchases and the uses of purchased commodities, as their means of accumulation. The capitalist throws money into circulation in order to have money return in a greater quantity. The merchant buys low to sell high. The moneylender lends money to collect this money with interest.19placeholder The industrialist buys the labor power of workers to consume this labor power, produce commodities, and sell these commodities for profit.20placeholder The stock trader buys stocks in anticipation of a rise of value to sell these stocks.21placeholder Purchases, and, in general, activities which require the spending of money, e.g. moneylending, confront the capitalist not as their enemy, but as their means of accumulation. Their uses of purchased commodities, likewise, confront the capitalist not as their enemy, but as their means of accumulation: commodities bought by the merchant and stock trader are commodities usable in sales to accumulate money. The labor power bought by the industrialist is a commodity usable in the production of commodities for sale and accumulation of money. Finally, the quantity of money the capitalist acquires, too, confronts the capitalist not as money to be hoarded, i.e. not used, but as money to be thrown back into circulation to make more money, in other words, as their means of accumulation.
- This sublation of the other of the miser, however, restores in full, within the operative consciousness of capital, the preoccupation with use which is disrupted in hoarding. This preoccupation, of course, is not a preoccupation with use for the sake of satisfying needs, but use for the sake of accumulating money, but these uses remain uses which cannot occur until after exchange has been completed, and whose mutual exclusion with exchange, due to the capitalist’s preoccupation with use, cannot be realized.
- The resolution to the conflict of consciousnesses is to be found in the continuation of this movement. Reflective consciousness, reflecting on the movement of operative consciousness and learning its language, so to speak, becomes, also, able to speak to operative consciousness in its own language and guide its movement to the conclusion reflective consciousness desires.
8. The proletariat and the bourgeoisie
“The history of all countries shows that the working class, exclusively by its own efforts, is able to develop only trade union consciousness…The theory of socialism, however, grew out of the philosophic, historical, and economic theories elaborated by the educated representatives of the propertied classes, by intellectuals”.22placeholder
-
- In the first place, we do not find among workers the condition for the realization of the implicit negativity of their operative consciousness of exchange and, therefore, also the conflict of consciousnesses. The subsistence wages they are paid do not permit them the luxury of hoarding. Workers are entirely consumed in their efforts to survive, i.e. their sale of their labor power, wage labor under industrialists, and reproduction of their labor power. Having said so, workers, in their efforts to survive, already come together to form trade unions to demand better wages and benefits.
- We find among capitalists the condition for the realization of the implicit negativity of their operative consciousness of exchange and the conflict of consciousnesses. Capitalists engage, for the most parts, in capital, but their economic conditions, unlike those of workers, are no obstacle to their engaging in hoarding as well. In simultaneity, however, capitalists also compete among themselves. Triumphs and defeats in their competition develop within capitalists conflicting sentiments. Every triumph affirms their desire for money and the means by which they have accumulated money. Every loss develops within capitalists resentment for other capitalists and a misguided feeling of kinship with workers: they have felt, in their wallet, the oppression of other capitalists. Their business acumen also develops within them an opportunism which sees cooperation with workers as a means to re-gaining their wealth and standing among the bourgeoisie. Myriad directions in which capitalists seek the resolution of their conflict of consciousnesses emerge from their conflicting sentiments. Apologists, reformers, opportunists, and revolutionaries come into being. More generally, their directions can be divided into two: among the bourgeoisie, through their continued pursuits of profit and the evolution of capital their pursuits stand to bring about, and among the proletariat, through their efforts to establish a new mode, or modes, of exchange where they and workers alike enjoy more dignified lives.
- Capitalists who sympathize with workers approach workers and find workers too consumed in their efforts to survive to imagine a future which is not a repetition of the present. Capitalists, therefore, take it upon themselves to design ideal societies which promise themselves and workers more dignified lives and, therefore, rouse the workers, and where, more importantly, their conflict of consciousnesses is resolved, or stands to be resolved. Capitalists exhaust their intellect and resources to promote their designs through publications and model experiments. The scale and efficacy of their efforts are, however, inevitably, limited by their intellect and resources. Their designs are limited by their social experience. The number of printing presses they can enlist, the scale of their model experiments, and so forth, are limited by their wealth.
- The utopian efforts of capitalists move the reformers of capital to tears, who double their efforts to improve the economic conditions of workers. The utopian efforts of capitalists, the efforts of reformers, and, finally, the efforts of trade unions together improve the economic conditions of workers, which, finally, permit workers the luxury of hoarding. Workers secure for themselves the condition for the realization of the implicit negativity of their consciousness of exchange and the conflict of consciousnesses. In simultaneity, the utopian efforts of capitalists also educate workers who, therefore, gain visions of ideal societies where they enjoy more dignified lives, or, better yet, have lived these visions in model experiments. Educated workers and capitalists who sympathize with workers come together to form political parties, both to defend the interests of workers in a society which has become more sympathetic to the plight of workers, and to perfect the designs and theories produced in the previous utopian efforts of capitalists. Political parties, unlike the utopian efforts of capitalists, do not depend on the intellect and resources of capitalists alone, but capitalists and workers both. Therefore, the scale of the parties’ activities can be expanded through the expansion of their membership, and the efficacy of their methods increased through continuous development. Designs and theories produced in the utopian efforts of capitalists are mastered by workers, tested against social reality in praxis and the combined social experiences of capitalists and workers in theoretical criticism, and gradually perfected through repeated praxis and criticism. In simultaneity, as the political parties have both bourgeois and proletarian members, their unity is, inevitably, riven by class differences, and, even, conflicts. Members of the political parties make constant efforts to preserve the unity of the parties against these differences and conflicts, e.g. through democratic centralism, purges, the practice of self-criticism, and so forth.
- In their defense of the interests of workers, the political parties enter into alliances with trade unions, unaffiliated workers, bourgeois reformers, and opportunists. Factions unite against the oppression of capitalists who have exploited workers and triumphed against other capitalists. The unity of the alliances, however, mask conflicts which continue underground. Political parties strive to expand their membership and spread their influence into the ranks of their allies. Bourgeois reformers and opportunists continue, outside of the alliances, to exploit workers. Within the alliances, they maintain a tenuous friendship with their allies: as soon as the alliances have become expressly anti-capitalist, their wealth and standing among the bourgeoisie have been re-gained, or they see they stand to do so through other means, they abandon their allies for the bourgeoisie. Factions are absorbed, subjugated, driven out, or leave by themselves. The balance of power within the alliances is gradually unbalanced. Subterranean conflicts come into the open. The alliances collapse.
- In addition to open conflicts, stabler alliances also emerge from the ruins of the collapsed alliances. The political parties which triumphed in the subterranean conflicts of the collapsed alliances have expanded their membership and gained firmer allies. Having said so, political parties, having witnessed the collapses of the previous alliances and contributed to the collapses, also take precautions against the collapses of their new alliances. Control, direct or indirect, is exerted over its allies to suppress any subterranean conflict, or ensure subterranean conflicts do not escalate to the point they tear the alliances apart. Hence, where the collapsed alliances are nominal alliances between factions which continue their conflicts underground, the new alliances are nominal alliances between the triumphant political parties and their subsidiary organizations, whose difference and independence from the triumphant parties are in name alone.
- Political parties expand their sphere of influence through collapsed alliances. They gradually gain an advantage over the bourgeoisie, and, even, succeed in subjugating the bourgeoisie to a level, e.g. through the establishment of a dictatorship of the proletariat in a nation. As soon as they have done so, the bourgeoisie no longer confronts the political parties as their enemy, but as their enemy whom they have subjugated. In their confrontation with the bourgeoisie, they are also confronted with themselves, or their subjugation of the bourgeoisie. The internal divisions of the political parties and their subsidiary organizations gradually become the object of consciousness of every member of the parties and their subsidiary organizations. The political parties have arrived at a critical juncture. They have gained a solid foothold in their conflicts with the bourgeoisie and must maintain this foothold. The task of preserving the unity of the political parties and their subsidiary organizations against their internal divisions, i.e. class differences and conflicts between bourgeois and proletarian members, become urgent. If they have, previously, overlooked their internal divisions in order to, more effectively, combat the bourgeoisie, they no longer have any choice, on the subjugation of the bourgeoisie, but to confront their internal divisions. As a result, however, proletarian members become suspicious of bourgeois members and look upon them as potential, or, even, outright, enemies. Bourgeois members, looking at themselves through the eyes of proletarian members, become paranoid. Genuine opportunists fear exposure and double down on their deception to manipulate the internal conflicts to their favor. Committed members fall into a conflict between their commitment to the parties and their perception by other members. The unity of the political parties and their subsidiary organizations is fractured by the very efforts of its members to preserve their unity.
- As the unity of the political parties and their subsidiary organizations becomes fractured, the subjugated bourgeoisie combines forces with unsubjugated bourgeois elements, e.g. foreign bourgeois states, and rises in rebellion, e.g. civil war. Their rebellion escalates internal conflicts within the political parties and their subsidiary organizations, as members who are in favor of continuing internal conflicts, having already pressed myriad charges against the members they aim to persecute, have gained another: they blame other members for the parties and subsidiary organizations’ failure to subjugate the bourgeoisie. In simultaneity, the rebellion of the bourgeoisie also provokes a response from the persecuted members who, having already a cause to be critical of the internal conflicts, have gained another: they take their persecutors to task for weakening the unity of the parties and subsidiary organizations. These members enter into conflict with others who wish to continue the internal conflicts. The result of this conflict is determined by the strength of the rebelling bourgeoisie, and the extent of persecution within the political parties and their subsidiary organizations, which determines the strength of the two conflicting factions. The rebelling bourgeoisie either becomes freed from their subjugator who collapses from within, or a new order emerges within the political parties and their subsidiary organizations, where one faction triumphs over the other and gains supremacy, as well as a new order without, as the reformed parties and subsidiary organizations restore their subjugation of the bourgeoisie.
- In the movement from the efforts of workers to survive and the division of the bourgeoisie, to the collapses or reformations of political parties and their subsidiary organizations, and their failure to, or subjugation, of the bourgeoisie, the conflict of consciousness ceases to be a conflict between the theory and practice of the bourgeoisie. It becomes conflicts within and between political organizations and social classes. Reflective consciousness ceases to be the theory of the bourgeoisie. It becomes, in the movement, the utopian efforts of capitalists, political parties, persecuted factions in political parties and their subsidiary organizations, and so forth. The corresponding operative consciousnesses are workers (utopian efforts of capitalists), the utopian efforts of capitalists, allies of the political parties, the political parties and their subsidiary organizations (political parties), persecuting factions within the parties and subsidiary organizations (persecuted factions), and so forth. The implicit negativity of the operative consciousness of the practical mode of exchange announces itself in every reflective consciousness. It heralds war in every corner of society. On the end of the movement, the conflict of consciousnesses is still unresolved. Reflective consciousness is still required to reflect on the movement of operative consciousness, learn its language, and guide it to achieve the resolution of its conflict with reflective consciousness.
- The movement of consciousness does not terminate on the resolution of the conflict of consciousnesses. Rather, the movement of consciousness is, potentially, infinite. As soon as the division between subject and object has emerged, the subject has constituted the object, in its confrontation with the constituted object, been confronted with itself and become self-conscious, and, finally, achieved a consciousness of its self-consciousness, an infinite regress threatens. The consciousness of self-consciousness can discover, within self-consciousness, a more fundamental incompleteness than the implicit negativity we have discussed. Self-consciousness does not include within itself its own subject, i.e. the subject which is conscious of itself in self-consciousness. Self-consciousness is, therefore, incomplete and, outside of self-consciousness, is an unconscious remainder of the subject. Efforts to include this reminder of the subject within self-consciousness, succeeding in including this remainder also reproduce this remainder outside of self-consciousness as a second unconscious remainder. The infinite regress which threatens is an infinite series of incomplete self-consciousnesses and unconscious remainders of the subject. Each unconscious remainder is also always included in the subsequent self-consciousness in the series. This infinite regress, or movement from self-consciousness to self-consciousness, is a potential of consciousness. Consciousness has already been thrown into the proximity of this potential by the conflict of consciousnesses and its efforts to resolve this conflict. Its self-objectification and pursuit of complete and unified self-knowledge prepare it for a final and eternal journey. On the resolution of the conflict of consciousnesses, consciousness is set to embark on this journey.
If we flee, we gain one.
If we advance, two.
Works Cited
Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by D.P. Chase. Wikisource.
Karatani, Kōjin. The Structure of World History. Translated by Michael K. Bourdaghs. Durham and London: Duke University Press, 2014.
Lenin, Vladimir. “What is to be Done?” In Lenin’s Selected Works Volume 1, 119-271. Translated by Joe Fineberg and George Hanna. Marxists Internet Archive.
Marx, Karl. Capital, Volume 1. Translated by Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling. Marxists Internet Archive.
— . Capital, Volume 3. Edited by Friedrich Engels. Translated by Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling. Marxists Internet Archive.
Smith, Adam. The Wealth of Nations. Wikisource.
Sohn-Rethel, Alfred. Intellectual and Manual Labour. Translated by Martin Sohn-Rethel. Leiden and Boston: Brill, 2021.
Alfred Sohn-Rethel, Intellectual and Manual Labour, trans. Martin Sohn-Rethel (Leiden and Boston: Brill, 2021), 23, https://files.libcom.org/files/alfred-sohn-rethel-intellectual-and-manual-labor-a-critique-of-epistemology1.pdf.
Alfred Sohn-Rethel, Intellectual and Manual Labour, trans. Martin Sohn-Rethel (Leiden and Boston: Brill, 2021), 19.
Alfred Sohn-Rethel, Intellectual and Manual Labour, trans. Martin Sohn-Rethel (Leiden and Boston: Brill, 2021), 21.
Alfred Sohn-Rethel, Intellectual and Manual Labour, trans. Martin Sohn-Rethel (Leiden and Boston: Brill, 2021), 22.
Karl Marx, Capital, Volume 1, trans. Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling (Marxists Internet Archive), https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch01.htm#S1. Of course, this section is informed more by Martin Heidegger’s tool analysis in Being and Time than the concept of use-value. For more concise and clearer summaries of Heidegger’s thought than any I am able to write, see, for one, https://epochemagazine.org/12/heideggers-the-being-of-the-entities-encountered-in-the-environment/, and, for another, the section, “Being-in-the-world”, in the SEP entry on Heidegger, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/heidegger/#BeinWorl.
Karl Marx, Capital, Volume 1, trans. Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling (Marxists Internet Archive), https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch02.htm. Other than the exchanges which occur between primitive communist communities, however, we may also think of the life of the modern human being, who, in early childhood, engages in practical activities using resources which are commonly owned by and accessible to every member of their family household, but, in their movement to puberty, is provided with allowances and, therefore, begins to engage in commodity exchanges with others outside of their household. Finally, in their movement to adulthood, they become a worker or capitalist.
Karl Marx, Capital, Volume 1, trans. Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling (Marxists Internet Archive). “All commodities are non-use-values for their owners, and use-values for their non-owners”.
Karl Marx, Capital, Volume 1, trans. Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling (Marxists Internet Archive), https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/commodity.htm.
Marx, Capital 1, https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch04.htm. “Use-values must therefore never be looked upon as the real aim of the capitalist; neither must the profit on any single transaction. The restless never-ending process of profit-making alone is what he aims at. This boundless greed after riches, this passionate chase after exchange-value, is common to the capitalist and the miser”. See also Karatani Kōjin. The Structure of World History, trans. Michael K. Bourdaghs (Durham and London: Duke University Press, 2014), 93, 94. “[T]he person who has money and the person who has a commodity are not equal. It’s a question of whether the commodity will sell—if it fails to sell, it has no value. The person who has money can always exchange it for commodities: it carries the right of direct exchangeability”. [I]nsofar as money has the power to be exchangeable at any time for any commodity, it gives rise to the desire for, and the concomitant practice, of accumulating money…The accumulation of money has to be distinguished from the accumulation of use values. The accumulation of capital is driven less by a desire for use values (objects) than by a desire for power”.
Marx, Capital 1, https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch03.htm#S1.
Marx, Capital 1, https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch03.htm#S1. “We have only to read the quotations of a price-list backwards, to find the magnitude of the value of money expressed in all sorts of commodities”.
Marx, Capital 1, https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch03.htm#S2a, italics my own. “The leap taken by value from the body of the commodity, into the body of the gold, is…the salto mortale of the commodity…money, however, is in some one else’s pocket. In order to entice the money out of that pocket, our friend’s commodity must, above all things, be a use-value to the owner of the money. For this, it is necessary that the labour expended upon it, be of a kind that is socially useful, of a kind that constitutes a branch of the social division of labour. But division of labour is a system of production which has grown up spontaneously and continues to grow behind the backs of the producers”.
Marx, Capital 1, https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch03.htm#S3a. “In its qualitative aspect, or formally considered, money has no bounds to its efficacy, i.e., it is the universal representative of material wealth, because it is directly convertible into any other commodity. But, at the same time, every actual sum of money is limited in amount, and, therefore, as a means of purchasing, has only a limited efficacy”.
Marx, Capital 1, https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch03.htm#S3a. “Commodities are…sold not for the purpose of buying others, but in order to replace their commodity-form by their money-form. From being the mere means of effecting the circulation of commodities, this change of form becomes the end and aim…The money becomes petrified into a hoard, and the seller becomes a hoarder of money”.
Marx, Capital 1, https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch03.htm#S3a. “In order that gold may be held as money, and made to form a hoard, it must be prevented from circulating, or from transforming itself into a means of enjoyment. The hoarder, therefore, makes a sacrifice of the lusts of the flesh to his gold fetish. He acts in earnest up to the Gospel of abstention”.
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics (Wikisource), https://en.wikisource.org/wiki/Nicomachean_Ethics_(Chase)/Book_Five. See also Marx, Capital 1, https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch01.htm#S3a3. “Aristotle…himself, tells us what barred the way to his further analysis; it was the absence of any concept of value. What is that equal something, that common substance, which admits of the value of the beds being expressed by a house”? Marx further argued Aristotle could not derive the concept of value, as “Greek society was founded upon slavery, and had, therefore, for its natural basis, the inequality of men and of their labour powers. The secret of the expression of value, namely, that all kinds of labour are equal and equivalent, because, and so far as they are human labour in general, cannot be deciphered, until the notion of human equality has already acquired the fixity of a popular prejudice”.
Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations (Wikisource), https://en.wikisource.org/wiki/The_Wealth_of_Nations/Book_I/Chapter_4.
Marx, Capital 1, https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch04.htm.
Marx, Capital 1. “As a matter of history, capital, as opposed to landed property, invariably takes the form at first of money; it appears as moneyed wealth, as the capital of the merchant and of the usurer”.
Marx, Capital 1, https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch07.htm, both sections.
On fictitious capital and stock speculation, see Karl Marx, Capital, Volume 3, ed. Frederick Engels, trans. Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling (Marxists Internet Archive), https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1894-c3/ch25.htm and https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1894-c3/ch27.htm.
Vladimir Lenin, “What Is To Be Done?”, in Lenin’s Selected Works Volume 1, trans. by Joe Fineberg and George Hanna (Marxists International Archive), https://www.marxists.org/archive/lenin/works/1901/witbd/ii.htm.