Issue #82 June 2025

The Way Out of Enframing: Lessons from Benjamin and Baudelaire

Arthur Dove, Sun, (1943)

“[Baudelaire] indicated the price for which the sensation of the modern age may be had: the disintegration of the aura in the experience of shock.”

— W. Benjamin, Some Motifs in Baudelaire, 154.

“Hence the idea that the cinema, as art of the masses, could be the supreme revolutionary or democratic art, which makes the masses a true subject. But a great many factors were to compromise this belief… if there were a modern political cinema, it would be on this basis: the people no longer exist, or not yet … the people are missing.”

— G. Deleuze, Cinema II: The Time-Image, p.216.


The concept of world-disclosure suffuses Heidegger’s thought. Where a phenomenological analysis of the way in which Being is relationally disclosed to human agents is present in Being and Time, the attempt to illuminate the way in which it is disclosed to us through language, art, technology, and inherited cultural-ontological understandings remains a point of foundational significance throughout his later writings. By interrogating the expression of this theme, we can trace the way in which Heidegger ultimately comes to understand art as the potential ‘way out’ of Enframing (Ge-stell) – that is, the technological understanding of Being that Heidegger views as fundamentally, and destructively, characterising late modernity. In investigating the relationship between world-disclosure and technology, Heidegger provides us with compelling reasons to reconsider, and indeed fight, the ceaseless techno-optimistic development that defines our present epoch.

At the same time, Heidegger paints a picture of human agency that not only misconstrues the nature of truth and its role in guiding critical, agential action, but is problematically restrictive of individual agency in its political-ethical implications. Following this, if we seek to meet Heidegger at the crossroads between world-disclosure and technology, we must then venture beyond his shortcomings, and in doing so revive the vitally important critical and active dimensions of a world-disclosive human agency. In the pursuit of this revival, this piece will begin by reconstructing Heidegger’s understanding of art as the way out of Enframing in some depth, in order to critically appraise his understanding of the interrelationship between technology, art, world-disclosure, and human agency. This will then open the path for, by way of Walter Benjamin, a turn towards Baudelaire’s poetic vision of modernity – one that sought, in its transgressive vitality and revolutionary impulse, to ontologically transform his epoch from within – as a vantage point in the search for what a twenty-first century world-defining artwork beyond Enframing might look like.

· · ·

To understand Heidegger’s conception of world-disclosure – and his view of great art as the potential way out of Enframing – it is vital to first understand Heidegger’s unique conception of truth as ‘unconcealment’. Heidegger’s later thought is characterised by a fundamental rejection of the dominant understanding of truth-as-correctness in Western philosophy (and Western society more broadly). For Heidegger, the assumption that the essence of truth lies in the correctness of propositional statements – that is, that propositional statements are either ‘true’ or ‘false’ insofar as they accurately correspond with the world – already assumes that entities are present in the world, and misses the more ontologically foundational phenomenon of ‘disclosure’, in which worldly entities come to presence and are thus originally revealed to us as existing at all. When one gazes at the stars, they appear profoundly differently to us today than they did to a medieval Christian subject – that is, as collections of subatomic particles, not divine, eternal celestial bodies – and this ‘appearance’ (an ontological coming-to-presence) pre-reflectively occurs in relation to our underlying, culturally-shaped understanding of reality itself. The correctness of truth-statements is therefore dependent on, and only intelligible to us through, a culturally-linguistically disclosed horizon of meaning; hence, for Heidegger, the dominant conception of truth as a “feature of correct propositions” is a culturally mediated understanding of Being, one that passes over the more primordial “disclosure of beings” as a whole.1placeholder

Building on this conception of truth, Heidegger argues that as art possesses the capacity to disclose worlds and unconceal the openness of the unrealised ontological possibilities available to us in the world, it represents the “happening of truth”.2placeholder In The Origin of the Work of Art, Heidegger argues that truth is achieved in art through its ability to unconceal the essential ‘counterplay’ or ‘strife’ between ‘earth’ and ‘world’. For Heidegger, ‘earth’ refers to the primordial material base from which entities can come forth, and ‘world’ refers to the ontological sphere in which this primordial base is imbued with meaning. However, insofar as earth and world are in consistent tension – the “setting forth” of the earth and “setting up” of a world in specific ways always simultaneously involves the “concealing” of other ways to imbue meaning on the earth – highlighting this tension allows us to view Being in its openness, specifically to the extent to which we can realise the myriad possibilities available to us for shaping the earth and disclosing worlds in different ways.3placeholder It is in this sense that Heidegger argues that certain (rare) works of art, such as Van Gogh’s painting of ‘peasant shoes’, allow truth to happen; through revealing the being of the peasant shoes as “what and how it is,” Van Gogh’s painting opens up the world of the peasant to us and thus “opens up (the disclosure of) beings in their being” as a whole, in a way that reading a theoretical analysis of nineteenth-century Dutch peasant life cannot.4placeholder

Here, the connection between art, world-disclosure, and cultural-historical perspectives becomes clearer. For Heidegger, the world-disclosive capacity of art allows it to reveal the shared practises, meanings, and ontological understandings that define a particular cultural-historical epoch. Art here serves to elucidate the shared norms and practises of a particular culture, making the implicit nature of this culture explicitly visible to its inhabitants in order to illuminate their shared understandings of their lives and ultimately Being itself; for Heidegger, art therefore represents “history in the essential sense: it is the ground of history”.5placeholder To take one notable example, Heidegger argues that the ancient Greek temple not only served as a significant cultural meeting-place and sacred place of ritual, but displayed and reinforced the cultural self-understandings that gave Greek “things their look and (people) their outlook on themselves”.6placeholder In gathering together the “paths and relations” in which central Greek values “[acquired] for the human being the shape of its destiny”, Heidegger argues that the temple constituted the “all-governing expanse of open relations” that provided the Greek historical world, allowing the Greek people to understand their lives in light of it. At the same time as opening up this ontological world, however, the temple’s tangible features “set itself back onto the earth” – with the “steadfast” stone standing against the storms and surging tides – thus giving it a dual sense of material precarity and permanence. In this sense, and in the same way as Van Gogh’s painting, Heidegger argues that the temple “[lit] up that on which humanity bases its dwelling,” namely the primordial, infinitely inexhaustible material base from which everything “arises” and everything “is brought back”. Heidegger thus argues that great art is not only poetic – in the sense of poiesis, or ‘bringing-forth’ a world – but that its poetic nature is necessarily tied to its particular cultural-historical context, insofar as it displays the tension between earth and world in a manner unique to the cultural paradigm from which it emerges. In this sense, as argued by Julian Young, Heidegger’s conception of art is not confined to painting or poetry, but includes any medium capable of bringing-forth a world, ranging from music and film to “world-defining… [cultural] events” such as “football games [and] rock concerts”.7placeholder

This ontological understanding of truth, art and history fundamentally informs Heidegger’s writings on technology, and prepares the way for his understanding of much modern art as an articulation and reinforcement of what he conceptualises as our understanding of Being in late modernity – namely Enframing, or the technological understanding of Being. For Heidegger, the modern (Western) understanding of Being is one of Cartesian ‘subjectivism’, in which human beings understand themselves as individual ‘subjects’ and worldly entities as distinct, external ‘objects’. Following this, Heidegger argues that the modern tendency to view the world as something ‘out there’ and ‘separate’ from our individual selves has transformed into ‘Enframing’ in late modernity, in which worldly entities are understood not only as independent objects but as objective resources to be utilised. In The Question Concerning Technology, Heidegger argues that the characteristic features of late-modern thinking – the technological and scientific aspirations to calculate, order and master an ‘objective reality’ – have rendered the world a “storehouse” that is valuable only insofar as it can be optimised for instrumental purposes.8placeholder For Heidegger, such a ‘technological’ understanding of Being is deeply problematic. Firstly, in reducing the value of worldly entities to instrumental purposes, Enframing renders worldly entities (including other human beings) intrinsically meaningless beyond their potential usage in furthering technological development; this in turn constructs a nihilistic ontology in which our existence is reduced to the ever-expanding technological domination of the world for no broader purpose beyond technological growth itself. Furthermore, Heidegger argues that as Enframing is one way of truth happening – to be precise, through unconcealing Being as a “standing-reserve” of resources to be efficiently ordered and instrumentally optimised – it represents an extreme ontological danger that threatens to imprison us: through asserting itself as the “ostensibly sole way of revealing” the world, Enframing “blocks the shining-forth” of other modes of world-disclosure and denies us the possibility of more “original” and “free” ways of understanding Being.9placeholder

Tying into this, for Heidegger this epochal understanding of Being is rearticulated in our modern ‘aesthetic’ understanding of art, in which artworks become objects to be analysed in terms of the subjective experiences of both viewers and artists. For example, contemporary artworks such as paintings and films are displayed as objects to be perceived in galleries and cinemas, which individuals attend in order to seek desired effects on themselves (such as the affective experience of beauty or catharsis), and artists creatively contribute to in the willing attempt to produce such desired effects. In this sense, Heidegger argues that late-modern artworks are understood as aesthetic resources, with their value instrumentally calculated in terms of the subjective feelings that they are capable of producing. For Heidegger, this calculative understanding of art thus mirrors and reinforces the culturally and ontologically problematic logic of Enframing – in modern art, as in the modern age more broadly, “man becomes the relational centre of that which is as such”.10placeholder

Despite this, as Heidegger conceptualises art as having revolutionary cultural-ontological potential – that is, through its ability to both disclose worlds and ground cultural understandings of being – Heidegger argues that it is art that is uniquely capable of transforming the technological understanding of Being that dominates late modernity. For Heidegger, such a revolutionary change cannot be grounded in an appeal to the past but must occur from within the cultural paradigm of late-modern Enframing, transforming certain aspects of our current ways of sense-making in order to disclose an intelligible reconstruction of our understanding of Being. However, as highlighted above, Heidegger does not view such great, ontologically transformative art as the potential product of the will of a certain artist; rather, Heidegger argues that the poetic “language” of a culture “speaks,” and great art naturally comes from within a culture through an artist who attentively “responds to [the] language” of this culture.11placeholder In this way, Heidegger argues that the world-transformative truth of a “poeticising” artwork would be already “cast towards… a historical humanity” from within, where it would have the potential to “open up” a truth of existence to be “preserved” by a historical people.12placeholder Following this, Heidegger does not claim to be providing examples of such revolutionary artwork, but simply preparing the way for it through illustrating the way in which certain artists (from Van Gogh to poets such as Hölderlin and Trakl) impersonally respond to Being. In a significant sense then, Heidegger conceptualises individuals as having a largely passive role within their culture, as culture essentially changes itself. Indeed, as Heidegger famously claims, “only a god,” or the organic emergence of a new cultural paradigm that grounds a non-technological understanding of Being, “can save us”.

As a result, for Heidegger the “saving power” of ontologically revolutionary works of art has two interrelated dimensions. Firstly, such artwork possesses the capacity to enter us into a free relationship with technology, in which technology can be utilised for non-calculative, meaningful shared practises (such as camping with friends) without enmeshing us in technological understanding.13placeholder Furthermore, Heidegger conceptualises art as capable of casting us into a free relationship with Being itself; one that recognises the inexhaustible, primordial mystery of the earth and the myriad possibilities for the poetic disclosure of the world, letting us poetically dwell as Being unfolds in its openness and abundance. For Heidegger, the ultimate potential for art is therefore its ability to disclose a way out of Enframing, towards ontological freedom.

Arthur Dove, Sun, (1943)

Heidegger’s illustration of the world-disclosive capacity of artworks retains pressing significance in our present historical moment. As technology has rapidly developed, the way in which we broadly engage with art and reality has transformed alongside it. For example, technological developments in musical production have occurred alongside an increasing late-modern desire to ‘own’ music, as music is increasingly stockpiled as a resource in the form of records, then CDs, then Spotify playlists. In the twenty-first century Internet age in particular, this desire for ownership increasingly applies to art in all forms; from Netflix and endless digital re-prints of masterpiece paintings on WikiArt to online recordings of symphonic orchestras and music festivals, the Internet has largely become an efficiently ordered, gigantic standing-reserve of art to be subjectively consumed for aesthetic enjoyment. Indeed, as Heidegger convincingly argues, this technological-instrumental understanding of art filters through to all aspects of our lives, including our understanding of reality itself. This is tellingly highlighted in the way in which the invention of the iPhone has prompted the phenomenon of individuals filming and storing videos of cultural events (such as live music and street festivals), reflecting a growing late-modern desire to not only own artworks but to own real-life artistic experiences themselves. Indeed, as such videos are often filmed for the purpose of being shared to social media, these artistic experiences are often further instrumentally optimised as social resources.

Following this, Heidegger is convincing in an important sense when he suggests that implicitly understanding art as an aesthetic resource inhibits our ontological openness. Firstly, when we view art and artistic experiences as resources, we approach them through this pre-filtered purposive lens and are closed off to experiencing the art or artistic experience on its own terms. Building on this, when reality itself is understood as a resource, everything becomes a tool to be efficiently used for our own pre-conceived purposes (such as enjoying certain artworks in order to make friends or reinforce ones existing worldview), and thus cannot be revealed to us in any truly novel or unique way. In this sense, Heidegger is not arguing that we shouldn’t appreciate the phenomenological experience of witnessing great art – as he claims, “beauty belongs to advent of truth” in art14placeholder – but is instead cogently suggesting that when we view art through a pre-filtered, aestheticised lens, it loses its creatively world-disclosive capacity and renders us stuck in this calculative worldview. Indeed, whilst individuals within late modernity increasingly claim to want to spend less time on social media, form communities not tied to technological-instrumental purposes, become closer with nature and gain access to more original forms of art, technological development and usage continues to grow at an ever-increasing rate, presently exemplified in the rapid, successful expansion of digital media, virtual reality, artificial intelligence and transhumanist technologies. Resultingly, Heidegger not only presciently illustrates how our contemporary relationship with art reveals our implicit technological understanding of Being, but how late-modern Enframing sweeps us away and imprisons us in its grasp, dominating our relationship with the world (and each other) and rendering us the “plaything” of technology.15placeholder

Despite this, insofar as Heidegger problematically neglects the individual capacity for critical agency within their culture, his ontological conception of art fails to recognise the ability of existing sites of genuine artistic resistance within late modernity to challenge Enframing. As highlighted above, Heidegger argues that individuals enmeshed in Enframing cannot instrumentally create an artwork to offer us a way out of Enframing, but must wait for the organic emergence of artwork capable of disclosing a new cultural paradigm. However, in assigning individuals this passive role within their culture, Heidegger neglects that individuals – despite being fundamentally shaped by the culture from which they inherit their values, ontological understandings and language – nonetheless possess a degree of critical agency within this culture. For example, the hermeneutic phenomenology of Paul Ricoeur cogently highlights the way in which Heidegger neglects our ability to “reinterpret our embeddedness in [culture] as an essentially critical stance,” through subjecting inherited understandings to critical reasoning, transforming them, and agentially acting on them.16placeholder Following this, just as it is dubitable that every ancient Greek and Medieval individual understood Being in non-subjectivist, non-instrumental terms – especially when we consider the prominence of notions such as self-interested hubris in early Greek culture17placeholder – it is vital to note that the largely dominant grasp of Enframing over late-modern culture is not all-encompassing. Indeed, consider the extraordinary diversity, range and complexity of artworks that have been produced since the beginning of the twentieth century; a countless number of these have portrayed an understanding of reality inconsistent with (and sometimes directly opposed to) technological Enframing, disclosing Being in myriad unique and creatively original ways. Hence, instead of passively waiting for a new cultural paradigm to emerge, we would likely have more success in overcoming culturally-dominant technological understandings of Being by paying more attention to existing artworks that disclose to us a non-technological understanding of reality, and encouraging the artistic creativity capable of engendering such cultural-ontological transformations.

This, however, appears to lead us to a crossroads. It is significant to consider here that the critical reasoning required for critical agency, through attempting to offer us an instrumental way out of Enframing in the form of deliberately crafted artworks, may remain trapped in the instrumental, calculative thinking that fundamentally characterises Enframing itself. We must thus confront the following question: is the notion that we can instrumentally transform artistic world-disclosure to show ourselves the way out of Enframing fatally self-contradictory?

I would argue not. Specifically, such an argument is grounded in a conceptual opposition between world-disclosure and correctness that not only ontologically misconstrues these concepts, but their relationship to truth. To the extent that world-disclosure can falsify reality – for example, ritual sacrifices throughout human history have disclosed and reinforced false ontological understandings in which benevolent food harvests required human sacrifice – it, on its own, lacks the vital critical dimension necessary for any understanding of truth at all. This is not to merely reassert the ostensibly naïve assumption of truth-as-correctness, but to highlight the potential for a reconciliatory understanding of truth as both critical and world-disclosive. As Nikolas Kompridis convincingly argues, through conceptualising the happening-of-truth and disclosure-of-a-world as the same phenomenon, Heidegger is forced to promote a conception of truth in which the capacities for disclosing worlds and giving reasons are made “mutually exclusive”. In doing this, however, Heidegger problematically neglects that truth can involve both world-disclosure and critical reasoning, and that this actually strengthens the potential for world-disclosure itself.18placeholder

Let us return to the potential for revolutionary cultural-events-as-artworks. Hubert Dreyfus plausibly suggests that despite its eventual failure to be culturally preserved, the ‘music of the sixties’ (embodied by Bob Dylan, the Beatles and Woodstock Music Festival) represented a potentially revolutionary form of art in the Heideggerian sense.19placeholder For Dreyfus, not only did this artistic movement embody a way of life and worldly understanding outside of Enframing – where “rationality, wilful activity and flexible, efficient control” were “made subservient” to the values of “peace, tolerance… openness, enjoyment of nature, dancing and Dionysian ecstasy” – but it freely used the technological “power of electronic media” in the service of these concerns. However, where Dreyfus re-emphasises the point that this movement arose organically, and that “a new sense of reality [cannot] be made a goal,” he rests on Heidegger’s dubitable ontological opposition between world-disclosure and critical-agential reasoning. Indeed, individual artists such Bob Dylan critically reflected on the culture of their times, and purposefully created art that critically responded to, and instrumentally attempted to transform, aspects of this culture from within. Furthermore, for enough people to “recognise” and “coalesce around” this new non-technological understanding of Being (a lack of which, Dreyfus argues, caused this movement to fail), non-artist individuals must not only respond to the new world artistically disclosed to them, but be able to critically resist opposing perspectives – for example, mainstream conservative stereotypes surrounding the danger of drugs and unproductivity – and use their agential capacity to indeed make a new sense of reality a goal (as the organisers of Woodstock did). Insofar as truth involves both world-disclosure and critical reasoning, our abilities to critically reason and agentially act in accordance with these reasons are necessary for the creation and preservation of culturally-ontologically revolutionary artworks.

This leads us to another significant point, one that further illuminates the fundamental flaw at the heart of Heidegger’s later philosophy: in neglecting individual critical agency, Heidegger is not only ontologically but ethically problematic, and finds his thought mired in an overly restrictive conception of culture and action. To the extent that individuals possess a degree of critical agency within their culture, they are (at least partially) individually and collectively responsible for their culture. Building on this, as we bear some partial responsibility for our cultural-ontological world, our cultural and artistic understandings and practises require some ethical concern with this world, unless we wish to argue – as Heidegger does not – that the ontological understandings and practises of our cultural world are unimportant. Following this, as artworks possess the potential to shape our cultural worlds, the ethical perspectives promoted by an artwork must be critically engaged with by the individuals within one’s culture.

Consider artworks such as J.M.W Turner’s Dido Building Carthage, or the rise of the Carthaginian Empire (1815). The painting depicts the founding of Carthage as a Phoenician colony, portraying a vibrant, sunlit landscape in which people bathe in the river and begin to construct the classical architecture of the city. In this depiction, the painting discloses a world of colonial exploration and cultural beginning; the earth is being materially shaped into a new (tangible and ontological) world, one that has carried over aspects from its overseas past and reshaped them in a novel (notably beautiful) natural context. Indeed, the influential painting – alongside similar seaport paintings by Turner and artists such as Claude Lorraine (who directly inspired the work) – in many ways articulate the colonial context in which they were created, an ‘Age of Exploration’ surrounding the unrealised possibilities available for Western cultural expansion and re-invention around the world. However, such a colonial understanding of the world directly resulted in widespread, and ongoing, exploitation, domination, and genocide. In this sense, opening ourselves to the world-disclosive capacity of such artworks must occur alongside critical-ethical engagement, insofar as uncritical engagement with them possesses the capacity to open or inspire deeply problematic ethical perspectives.

More viscerally, consider Leni Riefenstahl’s film Triumph of the Will (1935). A Nazi propaganda film romantically depicting Nazi German ceremonies and rallies, the film has nonetheless (despite its ethical content) been consistently praised as creatively innovative and stylistically “genius” by art critics since its release.20placeholder Not only were these acclaimed artistic techniques (successfully) harnessed by the film in the direct cultural-political promotion of Nazism during its rise, but its artistic portrayal of this fascist and genocidal political movement was profoundly Heideggerian; specifically, such artistic techniques creatively disclosed a mythologised articulation of a new, unifying cultural paradigm, one grounded in an internal transformation of historical German self-understandings and cultural practises. This illustrates the fundamental deficiency in Heidegger’s neglect of critical agency – where Riefenstahl’s film wholly evidences art’s world-disclosive, culturally-unifying capacity, it also wholly evidences the ethically problematic nature of neglecting individual critical agency, both in creating and responding to artworks.

Arthur Dove, Sun, (1943)

We may now turn to the poetry of Baudelaire, an artist in whose work we find a transformative world-disclosive capacity that does not neglect, but indeed springs forth from, a deeply critical agency. It is oft-noted that Baudelaire’s lyric-poetic depictions of urban modernity articulated the ontological character of modernity from within – as Paul Verlaine put it, the “profound originality of Charles Baudelaire [was] to represent powerfully and essentially modern man”. Simultaneously, Baudelaire’s articulation of modernity attempted to poetically challenge what he saw as its dehumanising, de-worlding aspects. Walter Benjamin, a thinker who consistently drew attention to the galvanising, emancipatory potential underlying our modern relationship with art, recognised in Baudelaire such a clash between revolutionary and self-abasing modern energies. In one sense, we can understand Baudelaire as a “classical poet,” as obsessed with visions of beauty and antiquity as he was with the depravity of modern life; affirming beauty meant not only wilfully recognising it in the background of the everyday, but affirming the beauty of the darkness, violence and sensuality present in natural, vital energies, energies that had been twisted but remained latently powerful in modernity.21placeholder Yet in another sense, Benjamin leads us to understand Baudelaire as the uniquely great modern artist – one who not only presents us with a vision of the world beyond the atomised technologisation of modernity, but does so by critically speaking through modernity, shaping modernity to reveal both its enriching and stifling impulses on its own terms.

The Paris of the Second Empire in Baudelaire captures Benjamin’s interpretation of Baudelaire’s cultural-political significance in its greatest richness and depth. Benjamin begins the essay weaving through Baudelaire, Marx, and revolutionary activist Louis Auguste Blanqui, painting a picture of nineteenth-century urban life through the lens of industrialisation and the political-economic struggles that it gave rise to. At the same time, Benjamin sees in Baudelaire a unique appreciation for the novelty of modernity, interrogating not only essentially modern character-types such as the revolutionary bohème and the flâneur, but the phenomenological experience of the rushing, amorphous urban crowd. For Baudelaire, modern life was characterised by such frenzied experiences, in which one found oneself simultaneously lost and individuated in their anonymity. In doing so, Benjamin constructs Baudelaire as a figure who “let the spectacle of the crowd act upon him” in a way that intoxicated him without letting it blind him to the “horrible social reality” of impoverished urban life.22placeholder Hence, Benjamin argues that through imbuing the modern urban world with novel, ontologically transformative meanings in his poetry, Baudelaire not only poetically brought-forth the modern world, but critically attempted to “interrupt the course of [this] world” and reveal that cultural-ontological developments and injustices are open to be challenged. Baudelaire’s simultaneous enjoyment of the fleeting beauty and grotesque, mechanical ugliness of modernity was thus only possible insofar as he was already “half withdrawn” from it, and attempted to “sunder himself from it as a hero”.23placeholder

“I give this verse to you in case my name,

A vessel favoured by a strong north wind,

Lands in distant epochs with some fame

And brings a dream at evening to man’s mind.”24placeholder

It is this state of half-withdrawnness that is of philosophical interest here. In the same way that accepting that we are not inevitably trapped in inherited cultural perspectives and are capable of critically reshaping our historically-situated standpoint requires moving beyond the conservatism that defines Heidegger’s (and later Gadamer’s) hermeneutical circle, spurring ontological transformation first requires not cultural immersion, but the partial withdrawal from one’s epochal horizon. This is what Benjamin refers to when he describes Baudelaire as the poet who conveyed the ontological “shock” of modernity, and yet constructed a transgressive vision out of the ruins of this shock.25placeholder And it is from this vantage point that, for Benjamin, Baudelaire came to see the hero – modelled on the form of the proletarian who required a gladiatorial constitution simply to earn daily wages – as the “true subject of modernism,” and sculpted his image of the artist after this heroic image. Modern life offered an assault on the “natural productive élan” of its subjects.26placeholder In response, Baudelaire saw poetry as a form of wilful hermeneutical labour that sought its own ancient, heroic, “Herculean” task: to “give shape” to modernity in order to revolt against it, to overcome it by moving through it.27placeholder

At the culmination of the essay, Benjamin draws attention to the following of Baudelaire’s poems:

“See, sheltered from the swells

There in the still canals

Those drowsy ships that dream of sailing forth;

It is to satisfy

Your least desire, they ply

Hither through all the waters of the earth.”28placeholder

For Benjamin, this stanza encapsulates the contradiction at the heart of modern ‘heroism’:

“This famous stanza has a rocking rhythm; its movement seizes the ships which lie fast in the canals. To be rocked between the extremes, as is the privilege of ships – that is what Baudelaire longed for. The ships emerge where the profound, secret, and paradoxical image of his dreams is involved: being supported and sheltered by greatness. ‘These beautiful big ships that lie on the still water imperceptibly rocking, these strong ships that look so idle and so nostalgic – are they not asking us in a mute language: when are we setting out for happiness?’”29placeholder

It is here that Benjamin locates the clash between classical and modern conceptions of heroism that he views as defining Baudelaire’s work. The task of the poet is to spur the oppressed, alienated individual into action, to rise from a state of indolence towards the achievement of greatness; this, however, cannot be done through the nostalgic attempt to revive a lost past, but through a unique reshaping of one’s present sociohistorical context. At the same time, Benjamin illuminates a pessimism at Baudelaire’s core, who views modernity as a tragedy in which true heroes cannot be formed, but in which the spectre of the hero is merely a part that is sometimes acted. For Baudelaire, ultimately the “high seas beckon to him in vain, for his life is under an ill star. Modernism turns out to be his doom. The hero was not provided for in it; it has no use for this type. It makes him fast in the secure harbour forever and abandons him to everlasting idleness”.30placeholder It is noteworthy that such pessimism towards the notion of heroism in modernity undoubtedly laces our present cultural-ontological climate.

Despite this, Benjamin maintains that Baudelaire was not forsaken but instead forged a unique historical space for revolt: for Benjamin, “Blanqui’s action was the sister of Baudelaire’s dream.”31placeholder Baudelaire’s poetic vision was not merely that of paradox, but that of a revolutionary strength that acknowledged but sought to overcome the paradoxical nature of the modern subject and hero. Hence, as Benjamin summates: “There is a special constellation in which greatness and indolence meet in human beings, too. This constellation governed Baudelaire’s life. He deciphered it and called it ‘modernism’”.32placeholder

In Being and Time, Heidegger characterises individual cultural embeddedness as “being-lost in the publicness of the they,” in which human agents, despite potential moments of seizing one’s own possibility for authentic existence, are constantly “falling prey” to the average mode of everydayness inherited from their surrounding sociocultural environment.33placeholder Baudelaire above all despises the everlasting idleness – the “ruthless vice” of “pallid indolence”34placeholder – that sees individuals accept and fall prey to stale, inherited cultural understandings, and at every turn presents us with a vision of life-affirming sensuality, of élan, of vitality, that rallies against decay, staleness, idleness and ennui. There is a fundamental connection between vitality of creative action and vitality of thought. Baudelaire’s heroic vision of poetry is that in which critically-guided action is not neglected but forcefully revived in the service of cultural-ontological transformation. It is a poetry that attempts to speak beyond the perpetual, hermeneutical tension that underlies the experience of the modern subject. And in a significant sense it opens such a perspective for ourselves, revealing that what is needed in twenty-first century late modernity is not a return to a nostalgic vision of a romantic past, but the emergence of a transgressive, communally world-disclosive artform that is both fundamentally from our epoch and beyond our epoch. Of course, the form in which such a unifying amalgamation of critical-agential and Dionysian energies may (or indeed, ever) emerge remains open.

Deleuze, in the quote with which I prefaced this essay, perceived something similar in the transformative potential of great artwork. Referring in his case to cinema specifically, Deleuze draws attention to the capacity for a fundamentally modern artform, a revolutionary and democratic “art of the masses,” to radically alter modern subjectivities and pave the way for a “people to come” out of a splintered modernity.35placeholder Deleuze’s political-ontological conception of art here bears further similarities to that of Benjamin; a recognition of its fascist potential when separated from critical agency,36placeholder and a post-Heideggerian emphasis on the potential for a world-disclosive “shock” to spur original thinking.37placeholder It may be argued that cinema missed its historical moment for such a task. And yet throughout What is Philosophy? Deleuze and Guattari construct philosophy as a concept-creating endeavour that may assist such a mass-transformative project, and do not seek the end of philosophy as Heidegger does. Philosophy here is likewise “not inspired by truth”, but instead retains foundational significance as the pursuit of the “Interesting, Remarkable or Important”:

“Criticism implies new concepts (of the thing criticised) just as much as the most positive creation. Concepts must have irregular contours moulded on their living material. What is naturally uninteresting? Flimsy concepts, what Nietzsche called the ‘formless and fluid daubs of concepts’ – or, on the contrary, concepts that are too regular, petrified, and reduced to a framework. In this respect, the most universal concepts, those presented as eternal forms or values, are the most skeletal and least interesting. Nothing positive is done, nothing at all, in the domains of either criticism or history, when we are content to brandish ready-made old concepts like skeletons intended to intimidate any creation, without seeing that the ancient philosophers from whom we borrow them were already doing what we would like to prevent modern philosophers from doing: they were creating their concepts, and they were not happy just to clean and scrape bones like the critic and historian of our time. Even the history of philosophy is completely without interest if it does not undertake to awaken a dormant concept and to play it again on a new stage, even if this comes at the price of turning it against itself.”38placeholder

It is in this space, in the half-withdrawn awakening of dormant concepts, that philosophy can clear the way for a necessarily self-reflective form of art. Enframing and world-disclosure are two concepts that must pressingly be reawakened and reshaped. Paying attention to the complex interplay between critical reflection and creative vitality, we can glean from Baudelaire a crystallisation of a world-interrupting and world-opening – that is to say, a fundamentally world-disclosive – human agency.

Harry Edgoose recently completed an Honours in philosophy at the University of Melbourne. His primary interests include phenomenology, philosophies of agency and temporality, and political theory, particularly the works of Arendt, Heidegger, Deleuze, Bergson, and William E. Connolly.

Works Cited

Baudelaire, C 1993, The Flowers of Evil, J McGowan (trans.), Oxford University Press, Oxford.

Benjamin, W 2023, ‘The Paris of the Second Empire in Baudelaire’, in H Zohn (trans.), Charles Baudelaire: A Lyric Poet in the Era of High Capitalism, Verso Books, London, pp. 11-102.

Deleuze, G 1989, Cinema II: The Time-Image, H Tomlinson & R Galeta (trans.), University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.

Deleuze, G & Guattari, F 1994, What is Philosophy?, H Tomlinson & G Burchell (trans.), Columbia University Press, New York.

Dreyfus, H 2003, ‘Heidegger on Gaining a Free Relation to Technology’, in D Kaplan (ed.), Readings in the Philosophy of Technology, Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, pp. 53-62.

Heidegger, M 2010, Being and Time, J Stambaugh (trans.), State University of New York Press, Albany.

Heidegger, M 2001, ‘Language’, Poetry, Language, Thought, Harper & Row, New York, pp. 187-208.

Heidegger, M 1998, ‘On the Essence of Truth’, in W McNeill (ed.) Pathmarks, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 136-155.

Heidegger, M 1969, ‘Seminar in Le Thor 1969’, in A Mitchell & F Raffoul (eds.), Four Seminars, Indiana University Press, Bloomington, pp. 35-63.

Heidegger, M 1977, ‘The Age of the World Picture’, in W Lovitt (trans.), The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays, Harper & Row, New York, pp.115-154.

Heidegger, M 2002, ‘The Origin of the Work of Art’, Off the Beaten Track, J Young & K Hayes (eds), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 1-56.

Heidegger, M 1993, ‘The Question Concerning Technology’, in D Krell (ed.), Martin Heidegger. Basic Writings, Harper Collins, New York, pp. 311-341.

Kompridis, N 1994, ‘On World Disclosure: Heidegger, Habermas and Dewey’, Thesis Eleven, vol. 37, no. 1, pp. 29-45.

Lovitt, W 1995, Modern Technology in the Heideggerian Perspective, Edwin Mellen Press, New York.

Piercey, R 2004, ‘Ricoeur’s Account of Tradition and the Gadamer-Habermas Debate’, Human Studies, vol. 27, pp. 259-280.

Sennett, A 2014, ‘Film Propaganda: Triumph of the Will as a Case Study’, Framework: The Journal of Cinema and Media, vol. 55, no. 1, pp. 45-65.

Young, J 2001, Heidegger’s Philosophy of Art, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

11

Heidegger 1998, p.146.

22

Heidegger 2002, p.20.

33

Heidegger 2002, p.30-32.

44

Heidegger 2002, p.16-18.

55

Heidegger 2002, p.49.

66

Heidegger 2002, p.20-21.

77

Young 2001, p.17-18.

88

Heidegger 1993, p.326.

99

Heidegger 1993, p.333-337.

1010

Heidegger 1977, p.128.

1111

Heidegger 2001, p.207.

1212

Heidegger 2002, p.46-48.

1313

Heidegger 1993, p.333-335.

1414

Heidegger 2002, p.52.

1515

Heidegger 1969, p.63.

1616

Piercey 2004, p.265.

1717

Lovitt 1995, p.719-721.

1818

Kompridis 1994, p.34-35.

1919

Dreyfus 2003, 60.

2020

Sennett 2014, p.45.

2121

Benjamin 2023, p.90.

2222

Benjamin 2023, p.59.

2323

Benjamin 2023, p.59-66.

2424

Baudelaire I: 53, in Benjamin 2023, p.89.

2525

Benjamin 2023, p.154.

2626

Benjamin 2023, p.75.

2727

Benjamin 2023, p.67-81.

2828

Baudelaire I: 67, in Benjamin 2023, p.95.

2929

Benjamin 2023, p.95.

3030

Benjamin 2023, p.95-96.

3131

Benjamin 2023, p.100-101.

3232

Benjamin 2023, p.95.

3333

Heidegger 2010, p.169-173.

3434

Baudelaire 1993, p.101-103.

3535

Deleuze 1989, p.216-217.

3636

Deleuze 1989, p.164.

3737

Deleuze 1989, p.156.

3838

Deleuze and Guattari 1994, p.82-83.

#82

June 2025

Introduction

The Way Out of Enframing: Lessons from Benjamin and Baudelaire

by Harry Edgoose

The No-Self, the Text, and its Ethical Aims

by Tara Yazdan Panah

The Affectivity of Sensations: Kant, Matter and his Metaphysical Principles

by Kasper Essers

Entrepreneurism: The Catalyst for Declining Political Engagement

by Oldřich Šubrt